Tope disjuction elimination along identity paths¶
\(\mathsf{rec}_{\lor}^{\ψ,\φ}(a_\ψ, a*\φ)\) (written recOR(ψ, φ, a_psi, a_phi)
in the code)
is well-typed when \(a*\ψ\) and \(a*\φ\) are _definitionally equal* on \(\ψ \land \φ\).
Sometimes this is too strong since many terms are not definitionally equal, but only equal up to a path.
Luckily, assuming relative function extensionality, we can define a weaker version of \(rec*{\lor}\) (recOR
), which we call recId
, that can work in presence of a witness of type \(\prod*{t : I \mid \ψ \land \φ} a*\ψ = a*\φ\).
Prerequisites¶
This file relies on some definitions, defined in
We begin by introducing common HoTT definitions:
#lang rzk-1
-- A is contractible there exists x : A such that for any y : A we have x = y.
#define iscontr (A : U)
: U
:= Σ (a : A) , (x : A) → a =_{A} x
-- A is a proposition if for any x, y : A we have x = y
#define isaprop (A : U)
: U
:= (x : A) → (y : A) → x =_{A} y
-- A is a set if for any x, y : A the type x =_{A} y is a proposition
#define isaset (A : U)
: U
:= (x : A) → (y : A) → isaprop (x =_{A} y)
-- A function f : A → B is an equivalence
-- if there exists g : B → A
-- such that for all x : A we have g (f x) = x
-- and for all y : B we have f (g y) = y
#define isweq (A : U) (B : U) (f : A → B)
: U
:= Σ (g : B → A)
, prod
( ( x : A) → g (f x) =_{A} x)
( ( y : B) → f (g y) =_{B} y)
-- Equivalence of types A and B
#define weq (A : U) (B : U)
: U
:= Σ (f : A → B)
, isweq A B f
-- Transport along a path
#define transport
( A : U)
( C : A → U)
( x y : A)
( p : x =_{A} y)
: C x → C y
:= \ cx → idJ(A , x , (\ z q → C z) , cx , y , p)
Relative function extensionality¶
We can now define relative function extensionality. There are several formulations, we provide two, following Riehl and Shulman:
-- [RS17, Axiom 4.6] Relative function extensionality.
#define relfunext
: U
:= (I : CUBE)
→ ( ψ : I → TOPE)
→ ( φ : ψ → TOPE)
→ ( A : ψ → U)
→ ( ( t : ψ) → iscontr (A t))
→ ( a : (t : φ) → A t)
→ ( t : ψ) → A t [ φ t ↦ a t]
-- [RS17, Proposition 4.8] A (weaker) formulation of function extensionality.
#define relfunext2
: U
:=
( I : CUBE)
→ ( ψ : I → TOPE)
→ ( φ : ψ → TOPE)
→ ( A : ψ → U)
→ ( a : (t : φ) → A t)
→ ( f : (t : ψ) → A t [ φ t ↦ a t ])
→ ( g : (t : ψ) → A t [ φ t ↦ a t ])
→ weq
( f = g)
( ( t : ψ) → (f t =_{A t} g t) [ φ t ↦ refl ])
Construction of recId
¶
The idea is straightforward. We ask for a proof that a = b
for all points in ψ ∧ φ
. Then, by relative function extensionality (relfunext2
), we can show that restrictions of a
and b
to ψ ∧ φ
are equal. If we reformulate a
as extension of its restriction, then we can transport
such reformulation along the path connecting two restrictions and apply recOR
.
First, we define how to restrict an extension type to a subshape:
#section construction-of-recId
#variable r : relfunext2
#variable I : CUBE
#variables ψ φ : I → TOPE
#variable A : (t : I | ψ t ∨ φ t) → U
-- Restrict extension type to a subshape.
#define restrict_phi
( a : (t : φ) → A t)
: ( t : I | ψ t ∧ φ t) → A t
:= \ t → a t
-- Restrict extension type to a subshape.
#define restrict_psi
( a : (t : ψ) → A t)
: ( t : I | ψ t ∧ φ t) → A t
:= \ t → a t
Then, how to reformulate an a
(or b
) as an extension of its restriction:
-- Reformulate extension type as an extension of a restriction.
#define ext-of-restrict_psi
( a : (t : ψ) → A t)
: ( t : ψ)
→ A t [ ψ t ∧ φ t ↦ restrict_psi a t ]
:= a -- type is coerced automatically here
-- Reformulate extension type as an extension of a restriction.
#define ext-of-restrict_phi
( a : (t : φ) → A t)
: ( t : φ)
→ A t [ ψ t ∧ φ t ↦ restrict_phi a t ]
:= a -- type is coerced automatically here
Now, assuming relative function extensionality, we construct a path between restrictions:
-- Transform extension of an identity into an identity of restrictions.
#define restricts-path
( a_psi : (t : ψ) → A t)
( a_phi : (t : φ) → A t)
: ( e : (t : I | ψ t ∧ φ t) → a_psi t = a_phi t)
→ restrict_psi a_psi = restrict_phi a_phi
:=
first
( second
( r I
( \ t → ψ t ∧ φ t)
( \ t → BOT)
( \ t → A t)
( \ t → recBOT)
( \ t → a_psi t)
( \ t → a_phi t)))
Finally, we bring everything together into recId
:
-- A weaker version of recOR, demanding only a path between a and b:
-- recOR(ψ, φ, a, b) demands that for ψ ∧ φ we have a == b (definitionally)
-- (recId ψ φ a b e) demands that e is the proof that a = b (intensionally) for ψ ∧ φ
#define recId uses (r) -- we declare that recId is using r on purpose
( a_psi : (t : ψ) → A t)
( a_phi : (t : φ) → A t)
( e : (t : I | ψ t ∧ φ t) → a_psi t = a_phi t)
: ( t : I | ψ t ∨ φ t) → A t
:= \ t → recOR(
ψ t ↦
transport
( ( s : I | ψ s ∧ φ s) → A s)
( \ ra → (s : ψ) → A s [ ψ s ∧ φ s ↦ ra s ])
( restrict_psi a_psi)
( restrict_phi a_phi)
( restricts-path a_psi a_phi e)
( ext-of-restrict_psi a_psi)
( t)
, φ t ↦
ext-of-restrict_phi a_phi t
)
#end construction-of-recId
Gluing extension types¶
An application of of recId
is gluing together extension types,
whenever we can show that they are equal on the intersection of shapes:
-- If two extension types are equal along two subshapes,
-- then they are also equal along their union.
#define id-along-border
( r : relfunext2)
( I : CUBE)
( ψ : I → TOPE)
( φ : I → TOPE)
( A : (t : I | ψ t ∨ φ t) → U)
( a b : (t : I | ψ t ∨ φ t) → A t)
( e_psi : (t : ψ) → a t = b t)
( e_phi : (t : φ) → a t = b t)
( border-is-a-set : (t : I | ψ t ∧ φ t) → isaset (A t))
: ( t : I | ψ t ∨ φ t) → a t = b t
:=
recId r I ψ φ
( \ t → a t = b t)
( e_psi)
( e_phi)
( \ t → border-is-a-set t (a t) (b t) (e_psi t) (e_phi t))